Life from the Ruins

How do the disciplinary histories we tell influence our scholarship?
As an undergraduate, I once took a course in Rhetorical Criticism and a course in Literary Criticism during the same semester. The two courses began on a similar note. The first week of Rhetorical Criticism covered the rise and fall of the “Neo-Classical” empire. The Literary Criticism course began with the story of New Criticism, from its inception to its dissolution. Both courses put their roots down in the tenants of ancient (disciplinary) history. We learned those tenants in order to understand what they got wrong.
This past week, when reading about New Criticism and Reader Response theory’s response to it, I rooted for Reader Response theory. I had a narrative in my head that went something like this: New Criticism was invented in the South as a precise and repeatable method for finding the Truth that objectively resides within any literary text. It had a seductive level of explanatory power, and caught on because it promised so much and seemed so simple. Then, inexplicably (as these things happen in the academy), this program became problematic. New Criticism, it was discovered, was selling snake oil; it was discovered that meaning did not reside in the text, that the meaning supposedly “found” by the New Critic was really meaning imposed by the New Critic. “Of course,” said everyone. In the presence of this epiphany, the question became, “So where is meaning?” And the answers were many: deep structure, or the reader, or narratology. And through these and other answers, literary criticism blossomed in method, scope, and potential as it broke free from New Criticism’s clutches.
I would argue that a similar historical narrative about Neo-Classical Criticism pervades our own field (restrictive monolithic paradigm reigns until diversity in theory and method shatters the paradigm’s obviously flimsy tenants), and that both historical narratives, like the dogmas they so happily destroy, damage their subjects through over-simplification. To name only one issue, the narratives do not discuss the institutional contexts in which the paradigm shifts occurred.  I’ve used the passive voice in the above paragraph because the crash-course narrative of New Criticism that I learned as an undergraduate left all of the people out of the story. Yesterday’s seminar put the people and the institutions into the story, and the story feels different for it. Before, the narrative had a ring of inevitability to it. Now, not so much. The debates I that I thought were settled now seem fresh – the wounds seem open, or at least poorly scabbed.
While reading about New Criticism for this seminar, I took issue with it, because in my narrative about literary criticism’s history, that’s how the story ends – with New Criticism in pieces after everyone took issue with it. I read Brooks and Wimsatt as if I was walking through ancient ruins, trying to learn where I came from, firmly understanding that I knew better than those who built the long-gone empire. The disciplinary history I had learned told me that the Reader Response critics, with their own flaws, were at the gates.
How much of our rhetorical theory and practice gets influenced by that same logic? “The story ends,” we all know, with Neo-Classical criticism in ruins. Good riddance, many would say. “Cookie-Cutter criticism” deserved to die. Ironically, we throw around “cookie-cutter” as a pejorative with little reflection. We cannot escape history. Our disciplinary histories at least deserve a second look, if only to make us more aware of how they impact us, and of how nuance might change the story completely.

 

Standard

Leaving the author behind

Our readings last week on New Criticism and this week’s readings on Reader Response focus on the text and the response of the reader to the text, respectively. There are a few similarities that can be pointed out including, as Tompkins argues in her conclusion, the assumption that meaning is the ultimate goal of criticism. Whether because it is irrelevant or unknowable, another assumption that New Criticism and Reader Response seem to share is a disregard for authorial intent.

This disregard for intent has been percolating at the back of my mind since the beginning of the class, and indeed even before. I understand the rationales given by both New Criticism and Reader Response for disregarding it, but it doesn’t seem to correspond to the daily lived realities of attempting to understand human communication. I say that because in so many other areas of human interaction and communication, intent matters a great deal. I’ll take up one such example below.

In this clip from season six of The Good Wife, Alicia Florrick and her law partner Cary Agos are representing a client that is suing a neighbor for patent infringement. The accused has been “saving seeds” from year to year, a process which is illegal if the seeds are patented. Both clients have decided to resolve the measure in binding “Christian Arbitration,” which is a mechanism for binding arbitration in civil suits outside of court, which revolves around Christian principles.  It’s an unusual setting for legal arbitration, but it articulates some of the questions about intent that haunt our legal system. In this clip, both lawyers argue over the role of intent. Does authorial intent matter? Or is it merely the ramifications of those actions that matter? Is someone breaking the law if they are ignorant of the law?

The answer of whether intent matters becomes complicated, both yes and no. And it is complicated in our legal system. For example, our legal system makes a distinction between premeditated murder, murder, and manslaughter. While the resulting loss of life is constitutive of a crime, the consequences for that crime are contingent upon intent. The law is concerned with intent and authorial knowledge. What did the author know? What was intended to be conveyed?

We measure intent within our legal system because we believe there is an ethical and moral difference between accidentally hitting someone with your car and plotting their demise. Can you imagine a legal system in which intent was irrelevant? If hitting someone with your car automatically meant life in prison? Intent is not simply a utilitarian calculation (if someone commits pre-meditated murder, they are more likely to do it again), it judges intent as being intrinsic to the meaning within the act itself.

Within the legal system, we believe that authorial intent can be discovered through an interpretive community, through a preponderance of evidence and through the hermeneutic of presumed innocence. The advocates involved in the case bring evidence of intent before the interpretive community (jury). This could be compromised of things such as eye witnesses, character witnesses, “hard” evidence, and the author themselves might take the stand to explain their interpretation of their own actions.

I understand that it is more difficult within the realm of criticism to weigh authorial intent. However, I am curious about the divide between what we believe we can or should measure in our material lives, and what we believe we can or should measure in criticism. Why is it that authorial intent is intrinsic to understanding the meaning of a death, and not the meaning of a work of literature? While a case of manslaughter may be interpreted by the “reader” with the same force as a pre-meditated murder, does that change the meaning of the act? Or is there something about authorial intent that is, in fact, intrinsic to the meaning of the action. If this is so, why are we in such a hurry to leave the author behind and what are the ethical implications for doing so?

Standard

Do I need a Totem for this?

The goal for criticism is to specify meaning. That was a major take away I gleaned from the reading for this week. Jane Tompkins’ essay, to conclude the collection, states that as a goal specifically and the other essays affirm that assertion (p. 201). I find this a provocative position. It offers the critic a very meaningful place in society. Arriving at meaning is a complex feat. This particular approach seems especially complex and requires a unique demand on the critic to go outside of the text, not only for context, but for the response of the reader. Full stop. Which reader? There were several interpretations offered by the various authors represented in the collection. For example, Walker Gibson proposes that the critic think about the “real” and the “mock” reader. Gerald Prince offers categories of the “real” reader, the “virtual” reader, and the “ideal” reader. Michael Riffaterre offers the concept of the “superreader” in order to analyze the meaning and effect of a poem. There are three separate ways to think about the reader, how is a critic to choose? Nearly all of the essays remove the author and their intentions from the equation of meaning. The context of the literature and history did not seem to need to be accounted for either. Jonathan Culler is the only one who seems to get us close to understanding context because readers make meaning based on publicly agreed upon conventions. One thing is certain, the realm of meaning resides in the reader’s mind.

There is also an intriguing moral and identity bend to this line of thinking. Reading offers the possibility of transcendence for Georges Poulet. In fact, the work “constitutes itself” inside the reader according to Poulet (p. 47). The reader gives life to the text. Reading leads to fuller knowledge of the Self and extends the creation of the Self for Wolfgang Iser. Meaning dwells in the mind of the reader for Stanley Fish. Norman Holland states, “Each reader, in effect, re-creates the work in terms of his own identity theme” (p. 126). Which implies that an identity can be surmised by the way in which a reader re-creates meaning and fantasy in a piece of literature.

At first blush, I assumed I would need to be a mind reader in order to do this Reader-Response form of criticism. Entering the mind of the reader is the task prescribed. How will I know what a reader thinks of a text? And, won’t every reader have their own thoughts about a text? Sure, there will be overlap here and there. But, really. How do I account for effects and results of a text? Diving into the mind of the reader seems to be a dangerous task for the critic. Is this approach only appropriate for literature? There are no examples offered in this volume that go outside of the realm of literature as the text. There is a lot riding on the reader and the critics ability to go into the mind of the reader in order to specify meaning. Yet none of the essays told me how to do this. Hopefully on Monday we can hash some of this out.

 

 

Standard

Why do we Choose the Texts we do, and What does it Mean for our Analyses?

What is the relationship between criticism and history? Between interpretation and fact? Or, as rhetorical critics would have it, between text and context? These questions, in particular, resonated with me because they center around my main anxiety as I approach my text for this course: what does my fascination with the text’s context have to do with the analysis of the text? I have chosen two anthropological “community reports” on “White-Indian-Black” relations in Robeson County, North Carolina. These reports, commissioned by the Rockefeller Institute, are some of the only documents that government officials could have used in the early 20th century to better understand the county’s complex dynamics. The texts initially interested me precisely because they helped me better understand the larger institutional context surrounding the 1960s/1970s civil rights movements in that same county. But, what role does the broader historical context–both before and after the text’s production–play in the analysis of the text, and does my fascination with the text’s context constitute enough legitimacy to submit the text to a “close reading”?

 

Before this weeks’ readings, I would have assumed New Critics would provide me with a quick, dismissive response. The New Critics were not, however, the naive formalists that I originally assumed. Many New Critics argued over the relationship between a text’s inner dynamics and the “outer world.” Does a text tell us about our personal psychology, feelings, ideology, history? Wimsatt Jr., for instance, begins in the final essay of The Verbal Icon, by describing the relationship between history and criticism as a complex and “problematic relationship.” Wimsatt Jr. identifies four distinct ways in which historical data can inform, expand, or distort a textual analysis. I think two of his distinctions were especially useful and important for critics to consider deeply: historical data as “antecedent” (supporting an understanding of the text’s origin) and historical data as “meaning” of a text (260). Far from ignoring the historical dimensions to textual analysis, Wimsatt Jr. speculated on the benefits and perils of using historical information in these different ways. He concedes that the text is made possible only through history, but emphasizes that every analysis and every critic is structured by the current historical context. Thus, even though I am fascinated with the historical context surrounding my text as antecedent, my own historical context is equally important to consider. An unchecked enthusiasm about a text’s historical context could easily lead into an “intentional” or “affective” fallacy and subsume the internal economy of a text under a personal bias or moral position. Perhaps Richards was not completely wrong in suggesting that a large part of a textual interpretation involves grappling with the reader’s cognitive biases. 

 

I think there is something to be said that if a critic believes a text to be a rich and relevant artifact of a larger historical context then the text deserves to be analyzed, in part, on its own terms. Critics, informed by a given historical context, should mine a text for its various textual dynamics and then use the historical data related to it as a way to further understand and perhaps challenge initially biased interpretations. In this way, critics can adequately heed Wimsatt Jr’s warning that “the personal interest is not the critical” (265). What do you all think, especially in regards to your own writing projects? How do we determine if a text is suitable for a close textual analysis, and how do we try to connect larger contextual matters to our interpretation? Is every “good” close reading the product of a back-and-forth interpretation between text and contexts, both past and present? In short, how do you plan on incorporating your text’s historical context into your analysis?

Standard